Tuesday, June 30, 2009
Fools of Time: Shakespeare's 124th Sonnet
Monday, June 29, 2009
On The Amusements of Men
Sunday, June 28, 2009
Politics & The Noble Hero: Coriolanus
The three plays, Julius Caesar, Antony and Cleopatra, and
Coriolanus, bracket the Roman Republic from its origins in the
early fifth century BC to the second half of the first century BC, when
Julius Caesar and his adopted son, Octavius, later the Emperor
Augustus, effectively ended it. It is easy to see why Shakespeare
should have been interested in the end of the Republic. Julius Caesar
was one of those unique individuals who seem in themselves to be
agents of historical change, and his assassination set off a struggle for
power that totally transformed the Mediterranian world. And what
could be more glamorous than the story of Antony and Cleopatra and
their doomed struggle against the cold efficiency, and luck, of Octavius
Caesar? It is not so easy to see what might have drawn Shakespeare
to Plutarch’s story of an obscure Roman hero from a time when Rome
was just another aggressive little city-state.
Fifth century Rome had, however, as Shakespeare knew from reading
Livy’s history, an active political culture which was beginning to
invent the institutions that would turn Rome into a republic. That’s
a problem for both Plutarch’s and Shakespeare’s Coriolanus: neither is
equipped by temperament and education to understand, much less
operate within, the politics of a Republic. The action of Coriolanus
turns on this fact.
Shakespeare’s Caius Martius (later, Caius Martius Coriolanus) has
been trained from birth to be a professional soldier and patrician
zealot, for both of which he seems to have a natural aptitude. His
mother, Volumnia, whom he worships, has been largely responsible
for his education. His father, for all we know, died before he was born.
He despises the plebians because they are plebians, and because they,
like most people, have neither his aptitude nor his love for war. They
are easily terrified on the field of battle and given an opportunity to
loot, they loot. Besides, they don’t wash their faces or brush their
teeth. They are, however, an important force in Rome, and in recognition
of this fact have acquired a pair of Tribunes to speak for them as
their representatives in the Senate. Caius Martius is implacably hostile
to this political innovation; he is our first reactionary. The other members
of his patrician class are not any happier about it, but they, unlike
Caius Martius, know enough to keep their mouths shut.
In recognition of his prowess in taking the town of Corioles, singlehandedly,
from their neighbors and enemies, the Volscians, he is
granted the surname Coriolanus; other rewards he disdainfully rejects.
He is politically ambitious, however, and when, as the Tribunes glumly
foresee, the patricians put him forward as their candidate for
Consul, he is more than willing. The Tribunes are glum because
Coriolanus’s political views are well known and they are pretty sure
that, when elected, he will try to abolish the Tribunate; as a war hero,
Coriolanus looks like a shoo-in. So it is a surprise to everyone when
he blows the election by failing to win acceptance of his candidacy by
the plebians.
All he has to do is go into the market place, dressed in a simple
gown, show the people the scars he has acquired fighting for Rome,
and ask for their votes. This he finds impossible. The gown of humility,
so called, feels worse than a hair shirt when he puts it on and goes
into the market place. What he cannot do is speak simply and directly
to the people he meets there, nor frankly ask for their support; the only
rhetorical mode at his command is irony. As for showing his scars in
public...! Such vulgarity is out of the question. He suggests that if
anyone really wants to see them, he might be able to arrange for a private
showing. All of this is conducted in a tone of subtle arrogance and
contempt—directed perhaps as much at himself for jumping through
these hoops, as at the people for expecting these things of him. Though
the plebians are aware that something’s not quite right about the way
their votes are being solicited, they are too simple and too easygoing
to make an issue of it.
[Had Shakespeare ever seen an election or a politician working a crowd?
Probably not. We are watching a representation on the stage of
something that no one at that time had, in all liklihood, ever seen before.]
When the Tribunes hear about Coriolanus’ behavior, they tell the
people they’ve been duped. They ask: Why didn’t you do as you were
told? This was your chance to get something in return for your votes;
you ought to have made him promise to “translate his malice towards
you into love,/Standing your friendly lord.” (II.3.190) Well, actually
the plebians had tried to educate him a little. When he had arrogantly
claimed that he deserved to be Consul and shouldn’t have to be
begging their votes at all, they had politely informed him that politics
is a two-way street: “You must think, if we give you anything, we hope
to gain by you.” And when he had cynically asked them their “price,”
one of them had gently reminded him of his manners: “The price is, to
ask it kindly.” (II.3.71-5)
The trouble with people like Coriolanus (and Bertram, in All’s Well
That Ends Well), is that they are uneducable. What had been nurtured
by their privileged, aristocratic upbringing, has become their nature.
(As Huck Finn says, such people are just naturally ornery—they can’t
help it.) Trouble starts when, coached by the Tribunes, the people
revoke their approval of Coriolanus’s candidacy. As the Tribunes had
foreseen, for they know him better than he knows himself, Coriolanus
is enraged. Soon he is saying what he really thinks, which is that the
people are cowardly, stupid, and undependable and shouldn’t have
any voice at all in the government of Rome. Either “pluck out the
multitudinous tongue”(the Tribunes), he declaims, or witness the decline
and fall of Rome. (III.1.141-161) Treason! cry the Tribunes and call for
the summary execution of Coriolanus who, spoiling for a fight, thereupon
draws his sword. And that might have been the end of Rome,
right then and there, had cooler heads among the patricians not prevailed.
Civil war is avoided and Coriolanus is given a chance to appear
in the market place and apologize.
In the following scene his friends and his mother try—belatedly—
to get him to understand the necessary expedients and hypocrisies of
politics; they try to teach him how to be a politician—and they fail.
Like Hamlet, he will be true to himself at whatever cost. Honor, for him
as for Hotspur, is an absolute good. Unlike Hamlet, whose self is layered
in irony, and a mystery to all including himself, everyone knows
where to find Coriolanus—and get at him, if need be. For he is a simple
soul, and perfectly authentic—the sort of man who, as Iago
remarks with contempt, wears his heart on his sleeve for daws to peck
at. And that, it seems to me, accounts in part for the incessantly iterated
word “noble” in this play which is almost part of his—Coriolanus’— name.
His is the nobility of a man who, in the words of Yeats’ sonnet, No
Second Troy, is “as simple as a fire”— and as destructive. Shakespeare
shows us, in Coriolanus, what it means to be absolutely true to oneself.
When his family and friends try to persuade Coriolanus to keep his real
thoughts and feelings to himself and pretend to eat humble pie, simply
as a matter of political expediency, he is indignant. Never, he says;
I can’t do that and I won’t. Why make such a fuss? his mother asks.
“You are too absolute; though therein you can never be too noble/ But
when extremities speak.” (III.2.39-41) No wonder her son is confused,
having been taught all his life that nobility is absolute; either you have
it or you don’t. Now, suddenly, he is being told that nobility admits
of gradations and modifications. To paraphrase Volumnia’s admonition:
Though you can never be too noble, for nobility consists in being
absolutely true to oneself and one’s principles, and such integrity is an
absolute good, yet extreme necessity justifies ignoble acts. Besides,
she continues, if deception is justified in war, as you will readily admit
for you have often said so, why not in politics? All of this being heartily
seconded by his fellow patricians, he has no immediate reply, and a
little later he reluctantly gives in:
Must I
With my base tongue give to my noble heart
A lie that it must bear? Well, I will do’t.....
You have put me now to such a part which never
I shall discharge to th’life. (III.2.99-106)
And that, as it turns out when he tries to play his part in the crucial scene,
is the simple truth: put to it, he is unable to pretend to be what he is not,
i.e. play the hypocrite. The Tribunes have only to call him a traitor
to put him out of his part altogether. For if he cannot give his noble heart
the lie, how can he endure it from another? Once more civil war is barely
averted, this time by the Tribunes who have moderated their demand from
death to exile, and this solution to the intractable problem posed by the
incorrigible nobility of Coriolanus is acceptable to all—all but Coriolanus,
who feels betrayed by his own class and exits, saying, magnificently if not
accurately, you can’t banish me, I banish you.
You common cry of curs, whose breath I hate
As reek a’ th’ rotten fens, whose loves I prize
As the dead carcasses of unburied men
That do corrupt my air—I banish you! III.3.123
He can no more banish Rome than he can step outside himself or
change his own nature. Nor is there “a world elsewhere”—his parting
shot—where he might have an easier time of it: the character traits
that get him into trouble in Rome would do so in any civil society. Even
a military camp, the only society he is fit for, would probably have to
reject him, eventually, as an impossible person.
He has to go somewhere, and the only place he can go, if he is not
to live as a hermit in a cave, is to Antium, the chief city of Rome’s enemies, the
Volscians. And since he is a soldier who understands war but nothing
else, there is only one thing for him to do when they agree to take him
in: join them in their war with Rome. The Tribunes had called him a
traitor, knowing it would enrage him; it does not occur to him, as he
goes over to the Volscians, that that is what he has just become.
Led by Coriolanus, the Volscian army is invincible, and soon it is in
a position to sack and destroy Rome. Emissaries from Rome, seeking
peace, are summarily rejected, but he can’t refuse to see his mother,
wife and child. For the first time in his life, he faces a tragic dilemma:
either he must break his promises to his new friends and allies, the
Volscians, who will certainly punish this betrayal with death, or he
must destroy his family by destroying Rome. Either way he loses, but
he sees at last that he can't take revenge on Rome for the dishonor it has
done him, without also destroying his family, and that this would be the
most ignoble and dishonorable thing he could possibly do. That should have
been obvious all along. Why does it take him so long to understand this basic
truth? Because he has always assumed that he is an absolute individual—
or as he puts it, the "the author of himself"—and therefore responsible to
no one but himself. He thereupon makes peace with Rome, withdraws
the Volscian army and, as he expects, is killed as a traitor upon his return
to Antium.
[Notice that Shakespeare is quite content to ignore the religious point that
the phrase "author of myself" raises for pious audiences. Jesus had yet
to be born; the Roman republic was happily pagan and would remain
so for almost 800 years; and Shakespeare was not the man to distract
his audiences with anachronisms.]
Coriolanus is usually thought of as a tragedy, though it is quite unlike
Shakespeare’s other tragedies—of all Shakespeare’s tragic heroes and
heroines, Caius Martius Coriolanus, is the least reflective, least
self-conscious, least attractive; it is also, in some sense, Shakespeare’s
most overtly political play though it is not clear what the point is or why
such a politically innocent hero should have been chosen to make it.
It is immediately obvious that Caius Martius is not a politician at all.
As the pure embodiment of the aristocratic principle, according to
which heroic greatness, manly worth, and moral power are looked
upon as gifts of nature, and consequently dependent on noble birth,
he is totally unfit for the complicated give-and-take of public affairs
in any large human community, especially a republic.
The play is set in early fifth-century BC Rome because that’s when
the rights of the plebs as citizens of the republic were being recognized,
and a radically new institution was being created, the tribunate,
through whom they would henceforth have the power to state their
grievances and have them addressed. All the people have rights in a
republic, not just those of a particular class, which is why a man like
Coriolanus, who can’t accept this new political reality, has to be ejected.
He thinks the nobility alone should have rights. He despises and
hates the people’s tribunes, not for intellectual reasons—his opposition
to this new and vitally important institution is not theoretical—but
because they are the people’s tribunes and his contempt for the people
is visceral, beyond reason. By virtue of his passionate loyalty to his
prejudices and principles, he becomes the catalyst that very nearly
turns normal class conflict into class war, and forces the people of
Rome, including the nobility, to banish him.
The absence of inward or reflective intelligence is what makes him
so pure an embodiment of the aristocratic principle. A more rational,
thoughtful man, able to examine and control his feelings and motives,
having recognized that they are a barrier to his political career, would
not have served Shakespeare’s purposes in this play, which is a critique
of the aristocratic principle at a moment when the English polity,
like that of Rome in the early years of the republic, was becoming
more inclusive and the power of the Commons in Parliament was on
the rise.
While Caius Martius is not only the perfect warrior but the perfect snob,
we fail to do him or the play justice if we leave it at that: as the
repetition of ‘noble’ keeps reminding us, Caius Martius has a moral quality,
which we rightly call noble, that lifts him above ordinary social distinctions
and above the opportunistic calculations and compromises
that characterize normal political life. Virtue, for him, truly is its own
reward, and the virtue that he prizes above all is what we would call
integrity—or authenticity, perhaps, which is not quite the same thing.
Unfortunately, the demands he makes of himself and others are inflexible:
come what may, he will be absolutely true to his idea of what or
who he is, as a man of honor for whom courage and honesty are
absolute goods. Nothing else matters, or so he thinks, until he is
brought face to face with his wife, child and mother outside the gates
of Rome.
Shakespeare in this play seems to been asking himself some such question
as the following: if the aristocratic code of honor cannot provide a morally
sufficient or even coherent ethics, what is the future, if any, of the aristocratic
principle in modern republics or commonwealths?
Caius Marius Coriolanus is a difficult person but Coriolanus is not a
difficult play. He would have been hard to like at any time, especially
now that the aristocratic principles he so intransigently stands for are
long defunct, but his thinking and his motives, like those of the
plebians, patricians and tribunes are not hard to understand. The
plebians want to be treated as citizens, with rights, which Coriolanus
and the other members of his class would like to deny; the tribunes are
doing their job, which is to protect the newly acquired rights of the
people against the obvious desire of the nobility to take them away.
Why otherwise would the nobility be so eager to have Caius Martius
chosen Consul? Since the tribunes themselves embody those rights,
they are necessarily protecting their own jobs (it could hardly be otherwise
since the one entails the other) when they are coaching the
plebians on how to deal with their enemy when he solicits their votes
in the market-place and, later, when the tribunes outmaneuver
Coriolanus and force him into exile. So the tribunes are schemers, so
what? Everyone in this play is looking out for his or her own interests,
or those of his or her class, with the possible exceptions of Virgilia,
Caius Martius’s wife, and he himself, whose patriotism is not hypocritical,
just confused. He truly believes that the nobility is Rome and
that the plebians are useless appendages to the body politic. To the
extent that they play a part in the politics of Rome, Rome will be weakened
and eventually destroyed. That is what he says at the beginning
and he never changes his mind.
As a man who is absolutely incapable of being false to himself,
Caius Martius Coriolanus shows us what it means to be unambiguously
noble: a person who can’t pretend to be what he or she is not,
and cannot therefore go back on his or her beliefs, values, principles.
Such a person—or idealized person—presents an insoluble problem for
the politics of a commonwealth, which is what England thought of
itself as, and was in fact in the process of (slowly) becoming, i.e. a
society in which everyone has rights and everyone has a stake in its
economic prosperity. The commonwealth or common good requires
that all classes, all stakeholders, make compromises. But when compromise
becomes the golden rule of politics, and the art of hypocrisy
becomes necessary for political survival and social stability, what happens
to the virtues of an aristocratic society: honor, integrity, courage,
nobility?
Coriolanus is a critique of aristocratic values but also something
more. What should we make, it seems to ask, of a polity and a political
language that no longer has any use for the word ‘noble’ except as
a metaphor? What will become of us when authenticity has become a
virtue that can only be excercised in private life? The play is ambivalent
about its hero because, I suppose, Shakespeare was ambivalent
about what these changes would mean. And so, I think, are we all,
even now as the politics of the modern, liberal republic hinted at in this
play—the politics of more or less democratic, utilitarian, free-market
states—is being established as the only game in the world.
Thursday, June 25, 2009
On Politics: some semi-eternal truths
Tuesday, June 16, 2009
Adam Smith on teachers & teaching:
Monday, June 15, 2009
A definition of 'liberty' from THE SPIRIT OF THE LAWS (1748) by Montesquieu
Saturday, June 13, 2009
The Idea of A Gentleman: Vanity Fair II
Monday, June 8, 2009
Vanity Fair I
When I had finished rereading Thackeray’s novel, it occurred to me that I ought to take a look at the book that he was alluding to when he decided to call it “Vanity Fair”: John Bunyan’s Pilgrims Progress.
Part One, written in 1678, is an allegorical account of the life of a good Christian, or at any rate the life of a man who wants to be a good Christian and eventually, after various encounters that test his spirit, succeeds: having reached the river of death that separates the Heavenly City from the world, he and his friend Hopeful drown as they are crossing it, whereupon they (minus their mortal graments) are taken up by a welcoming committee on the other side and brought in triumph into the City (which is everything you’d expect it to be: gold streets, harps, the lot.)
Any such life--the life of a wayfaring Christian--must, according to Bunyan and Christian tradition generally, be a lonely and heroic pilgrimage, surrounded by people, (like Christian’s wife in the first instance) who don’t see the point or, if they do, don’t want you to succeed and despise you for trying; or, in the extrreme case, try to kill you.
The first thing Christian has to do is leave his wife (spiritually, at least). Then he has to deal with various people who are so stupid or casually immoral that they get in his way--people like Obstinate or Pliable or Talkative or Mr. Worldly-Wiseman. And then there are such permanent features of the human condition, like depression (The Slough of Despond), despair, doubt, or the fear of death, or the sinful temptations that any moral person encounters, all of which have well-known names. For all of these Christian is more or less prepared, with a little help from his friend and advisor, Evangelist. What he is not prepared for--though Evangelist tries--is outright persecution by an enraged mob in the city of Vanity (where the Fair never stops) who rightly see him and Faithful as subversives who threaten the foundations of their whole (immoral) way of life.
The city of Vanity goes back to the very beginnings of human history (as Bunyan understood it). Here is what he has to say:
“This fair is no new erected business, but a thing of ancient standing; I will show you the original of it. Almost five thousand years agone, there were pilgrims walking to the Celestial City, as these two honest persons are: and Beelzebub, Apollyon, and Legion, with their companions, perceiving by the path that the pilgrims made, that their way to the city lay through this town of Vanity, they contrived here to set up a fair; a fair wherein should be sold all sorts of vanity, and that it should last all year long; therefore at this fair are all such merchandise sold, as houses, lands, trades, places, honours, preferments, titles, countries, kingdoms, lusts, pleasures and delights of all sorts, as harlots, bawds, wives, husbands, children, masters, servants, lives, blood, bodies, souls, silver, gold, pearls, precious stones, and what not. [I like that “what not.”] And, moreover, at this fair there is at all times to be seen juggling, cheats, games, plays, fools, apes, knaves, and rogues, and that of every kind. Here are to be seen, too, and that for nothing, thefts, murders, adulteries, false-swearers, and that of a blood-red colour. . . .Now, as I have said, the way to the Celestial City lies just through this town where this lusty fair is kept; and he that will go to the City, and yet not go through this town, must needs ‘go out of the world.’”
Faithful is judicially murdered--brutally lynched, essentially--but Christian escapes, when Higher Powers intervene, and continues on his way accompanied by Hopeful, one of the few decent citizens of Vanity.
The town of Vanity, with its eternal fair and its loathesome inhabitants, is at the center of what Pilgrims Progress is all about: a timeless depiction of the Christian way of life as one of unrelenting struggle with an enemy that is both within us and without: not only sinful, unregenerate human nature in the mass, as in the city of Vanity, but within us as well. Vanity Fair is eternal; it preceded the coming of Christ, which it ignored, and it will still exist, unchanged, when the Christian message has been forgotten. That, at least, is the plain meaning of Part One; Part Two softens that hard truth.
You don’t have to be a Christian to appreciate Bunyan’s intellectual and moral--and literary-- power: the human nature dramatized in this allegory is what it is regardless of one’s religious beliefs, or lack thereof, which is why Pilgrims Progress is one of the greatest books of practical ethics and morality ever written for ordinary people. Bunyan is one of the great masters of plain, eloquent, unadorned English prose; anyone who could read and possessed any books at all during the next 200 years, and more, owned this book and the bible.
Part Two, published in 1684 is a very different book: where Part One is timeless, independent of history, Part Two is all about time and change and, believe it or not, progress in the modern sense of the word. First of all, Christian’s wife has a change of heart and decides to follow him, with her four sons, who grow up along the way, marry, and have children of their own. When they come to Vanity, they find that it too has had a change of heart and changed: shocked by their extaordinarily brutal persecution of Christian and Faithful, this sinful city has become just another ordinary town. Where Christian and Faithful (later, Hopeful) had had to fight their way, these prilgrims have a champion, Great Heart, who accompanies them every step of the way and fights their battles for them. Theirs is a virtually triumphal ‘progress.’
The death of Christian, crossing the great divide, or river, is desperate and agonizing (Hopeful seems to have no trouble at all); when Christiana and her numerous progeny finally arrive at the river, those whose time has come go accross “by appointment” (as the Wikipedia article says); the others settle down by the banks of the great river and live out their days in peace.
What follows is a foot-note to Bunyan's description of the town of Vanity with its eternal fair. He was, as I have indicated, of two minds about its timelessness; and so am I. For the idea of an amoral place where everything and anything has a price and is for sale is modern and therefore historical. People have always known that money is power and that power corrupts but have held on to the idea that there are some things that money can't buy--in addition to life itself. So everyone knows, for instance, the famous (feel-good) definition of a cynic, as one who knows the price of everything and value of nothing, but not everyone understands that the size of the world economy is measured by illegal or immoral transactions as well legal ones: any transaction in which money changes hands. That is to say, there are very few things in the modern world that have value but no price. Such things as integrity, honor (not the boughten kind), courage, kindness, wisdom come to mind as possibly priceless goods, but that's about it. A cynic, like Shakespeare's Iago, is inclined to disbelieve in the disinterested practise of these or any other virtues; everyone, he thinks, has an angle, a price, and can be bought; it just depends on how much you are willing to pay.
The world is now one huge market, or fair, and this is a modern phenomenon. That market, or fair, was beginning to take shape when Bunyan was writing Pilgrims Progress, in the late 17th century. Hobbes' definition of happiness or 'felicity' in Leviathan (1651) lays the intellectual and moral foundations of the modern world-wide market-place. (See my posting of 2/2/08, "Happiness According Hobbes"). I've no idea if Bunyan read Hobbes. He wouldn't have had to.
Having gone this far out on my lonely limb, I might as well go little further. So far the corrosive power of big money and the world market in whatever the heart desires has been held at bay by the power of the state to maintain law and order. When the power of the state collapses, states fail. States are now failing faster than at any time since the collapse of the Roman Empire. Why? Religious extremism is one reason but the biggest reason of all is our insatiable appetite for illegal drugs. I have no idea how large the U.S. market for drugs is right now but it is huge and growing--especially now in hard times. With that money comes power. The power of money (and guns) is irresistable in new states, or states with democratic institutions including the rule of law which have only recently and with difficulty been established, or states where the struggle for scarce resources in a time of rapid climate-change has already begun. The states just to the south of the U.S., and in Africa are failing fast. The southern half of Italy seems well on its way. Afghanistan is a failed state; will Pakistan and the other Stans soon follow? And what of Russia, where the state has never been anything but tyrannous and the rule of law weak or non-existent?